Many catamorphisms seem to be simple enough, mostly replacing each data constructor with a custom function, e.g.
data Bool = False | True
foldBool :: r -- False constructor
-> r -- True constructor
-> Bool -> r
data Maybe a = Nothing | Just a
foldMaybe :: b -- Nothing constructor
-> (a -> b) -- Just constructor
-> Maybe a -> b
data List a = Empty | Cons a (List a)
foldList :: b -- Empty constructor
-> (a -> b -> b) -- Cons constructor
-> List a -> b
However, what's not clear to me is what happens if the same type constructor is used, but with a different type argument. E.g. instead of passing a List a
to Cons
, what about
data List a = Empty | Cons a (List (a,a))
Or, maybe a more crazy case:
data List a = Empty | Cons a (List (List a))
foldList :: b -- Empty constructor
-> ??? -- Cons constructor
-> List a -> b
The two plausible ideas I have for the ???
part are
(a -> b -> b)
, i.e. replacing all applications of theList
constructor recursively)(a -> List b -> b)
, i.e. merely replacing allList a
applications.
Which of the two would be correct - and why? Or would it be something different altogether?
This is a partial answer, only.
The issue the OP raises is: how to define fold
/cata
in the case of non-regular recursive types?
Since I don't trust myself in getting this right, I will resort to asking Coq instead. Let's start from a simple, regular recursive list type.
Inductive List (A : Type) : Type :=
| Empty: List A
| Cons : A -> List A -> List A
.
Nothing fancy here, List A
is defined in terms of List A
.
(Remember this -- we'll get back to it.)
What about the cata
? Let's query the induction pinciple.
> Check List_rect.
forall (A : Type) (P : List A -> Type),
P (Empty A) ->
(forall (a : A) (l : List A), P l -> P (Cons A a l)) ->
forall l : List A, P l
Let's see. The above exploits dependent types: P
depends on the actual value of the list. Let's just manually simplify it in the case P list
is a constant type B
. We obtain:
forall (A : Type) (B : Type),
B ->
(forall (a : A) (l : List A), B -> B) ->
forall l : List A, B
which can be equivalently written as
forall (A : Type) (B : Type),
B ->
(A -> List A -> B -> B) ->
List A -> B
Which is foldr
except that the "current list" is also passed to the binary function argument -- not a major difference.
Now, in Coq we can define a list in another subtly different way:
Inductive List2 : Type -> Type :=
| Empty2: forall A, List2 A
| Cons2 : forall A, A -> List2 A -> List2 A
.
It looks the same type, but there is a profound difference. Here we are not defining the type List A
in terms of List A
. Rather, we are defining a type function List2 : Type -> Type
in terms of List2
. The main point of this is that the recursive references to List2
do not have to be applied to A
-- the fact that above we do so is only an incident.
Anyway, let's see the type for the induction principle:
> Check List2_rect.
forall P : forall T : Type, List2 T -> Type,
(forall A : Type, P A (Empty2 A)) ->
(forall (A : Type) (a : A) (l : List2 A), P A l -> P A (Cons2 A a l)) ->
forall (T : Type) (l : List2 T), P T l
Let's remove the List2 T
argument from P
as we did before, basically assuming P
is constant on it.
forall P : forall T : Type, Type,
(forall A : Type, P A ) ->
(forall (A : Type) (a : A) (l : List2 A), P A -> P A) ->
forall (T : Type) (l : List2 T), P T
Equivalently rewritten:
forall P : (Type -> Type),
(forall A : Type, P A) ->
(forall (A : Type), A -> List2 A -> P A -> P A) ->
forall (T : Type), List2 T -> P T
Which roughly corresponds, in Haskell notation
(forall a, p a) -> -- Empty
(forall a, a -> List2 a -> p a -> p a) -> -- Cons
List2 t -> p t
Not so bad -- the base case now has to be a polymorphic function, much as Empty
in Haskell is. It makes some sense. Similarly, the inductive case must be a polymorphic function, much as Cons
is. There's an extra List2 a
argument, but we can ignore that, if we want.
Now, the above is still a kind of fold/cata on a regular type. What about non regular ones? I will study
data List a = Empty | Cons a (List (a,a))
which in Coq becomes:
Inductive List3 : Type -> Type :=
| Empty3: forall A, List3 A
| Cons3 : forall A, A -> List3 (A * A) -> List3 A
.
with induction principle:
> Check List3_rect.
forall P : forall T : Type, List3 T -> Type,
(forall A : Type, P A (Empty3 A)) ->
(forall (A : Type) (a : A) (l : List3 (A * A)), P (A * A) l -> P A (Cons3 A a l)) ->
forall (T : Type) (l : List3 T), P T l
Removing the "dependent" part:
forall P : (Type -> Type),
(forall A : Type, P A) ->
(forall (A : Type), A -> List3 (A * A) -> P (A * A) -> P A ) ->
forall (T : Type), List3 T -> P T
In Haskell notation:
(forall a. p a) -> -- empty
(forall a, a -> List3 (a, a) -> p (a, a) -> p a ) -> -- cons
List3 t -> p t
Aside from the additional List3 (a, a)
argument, this is a kind of fold.
Finally, what about the OP type?
data List a = Empty | Cons a (List (List a))
Alas, Coq does not accept the type
Inductive List4 : Type -> Type :=
| Empty4: forall A, List4 A
| Cons4 : forall A, A -> List4 (List4 A) -> List4 A
.
since the inner List4
occurrence is not in a strictly positive position. This is probably a hint that I should stop being lazy and using Coq to do the work, and start thinking about the involved F-algebras by myself... ;-)
来源:https://stackoverflow.com/questions/30810090/whats-the-type-of-a-catamorphism-fold-for-non-regular-recursive-types